ANIMALS ARE PEOPLE,
TOO
“Then
the Lord opened the mouth of the donkey, and it said to Balaam, ‘What have I
done to you, that you have struck me these three times?’ . . . The angel of the
Lord said to [Balaam], “Why have you struck your donkey these three
times?”
~
Numbers 22:28, 32
“Animals are people, too.” I used to say this with some regularly years
ago – before I ever dreamed of becoming an animal advocate and when I was
blissfully unaware of philosophical controversies over what makes a “person” – because
it seemed self-evident to me that animals were unique individuals with their
own viewpoints on the world and were therefore “people.” Fast forward several years to when I was
writing my proposal for my master’s thesis at Wesley Seminary. I included some
language (I don’t remember what it was) potentially attributing “personhood” to
animals. My advisor warned, “Don’t go
there. You don’t need to, and you’ll
only get yourself into trouble.”
Dr. Charles Camosy, professor of Christian Ethics at
Fordham University, has recently written a book entitled For Love Of Animals, Christian Ethics, Consistent Action.[1] In it, he argues (among other things) that
animals, as sentient creatures, are owed “justice.”
Christopher Tollefsen, professor of Philosophy at the
University of South Carolina, however, takes issue with Camosy’s views in a book review at Public Discourse (Part One, Part Two).
I not only think that Tollefsen misunderstands Camosy’s argument, I think
he misunderstands animals and those who care about them, as well as the
theological underpinnings of concern for animals, and in so doing he displays
many of the attitudes that have caused a great deal of suffering in the world. I think it is important to look at the
arguments he makes and why they are both incorrect and harmful.[2]
I apologize for the length of this post (and no pictures!),
but I hope you will stick with it. There
is a lot to cover.
Tollefsen takes issue with Camosy’s position that animal
welfare is an issue of justice. Camosy
defines “doing justice” as “being consistent and impartial in giving
individuals and groups what they are owed.”[3] Speaking specifically of Christian justice,
he adds that Christians are to be particularly concerned about vulnerable
individuals and groups in a context that is “skeptical of practices which
promote violence, consumerism, and autonomy.”[4] At the risk of doing violence to Camosy’s
position through extreme brevity, Camosy argues that animals, as sentient
creatures capable of suffering are vulnerable and are owed treatment that is
free of cruelty. Therefore, animals are
a proper subject of justice.
Tollefsen, however, argues that justice is owed only
among creatures who are “equal:” “Our
treatment of human beings [is] determined by the special kind of thing human
beings are. Beings which [sic] are not special in the way that we are, who do
not have the same nature that we have, cannot be the objects of the same kind
of moral concern that human beings are.”[5]
What sets humans apart, he contends, is “our rational nature, our nature
as beings possessed of a radical capacity for intellection and free choice" (emphasis original). These
special attributes, he asserts, set humans apart from all other creatures, make
all humans “persons,” equal to all other “persons,” and provides the foundation
for “the obligation that other rational beings have to treat humans with
fundamental forms of moral respect.” Justice
he asserts, is only owed among these equal “persons,” and is not owed to those
who are “fundamentally” not equal with “persons.”[6]
Tollefsen’s argument falls short in a number of
ways. It is incorrect and outdated as to
the nature of animals, it disregards suffering as a moral reference point, and
it limits the reach of “justice” to the powerful (or at least, those of “equal”
power). [7] There is, of course, a long history of this
kind of thinking, as earlier posts make sadly clear; it is a history grounded
more firmly in Greek philosophy than in Scripture and it leaves in its trail a
great deal of cruelty.
Tollefsen argues that “the presumption in favor of the
human” is grounded on the human capacity of “intellection and free choice,” and
that this ability gives to humans “an essential form of dignity.”
That claim, in turn,
finds theological expression in the view that human beings are specially made
in the image and likeness of God. And it finds further theological expression
in the claims that human beings were (and are) made directly by God, and for
God—that we are created to have a special relationship of friendship with our
Creator.
This is a classic example of what Richard Middleton means
when he says “many interpreters [of “image of God”] turn to extrabiblical,
usually philosophical, sources to interpret the image and end up reading
contemporaneous conceptions of being human back into the Genesis text.”[8]
We should, instead, start with what Scripture has to say and work our way
outward.
As a preliminary matter, Scripture tells us that the
animals were also “made directly by God, and for God,” so that clearly cannot
be the basis for setting humans above other animals or denying animals “justice.”
More substantively, I’m not sure exactly what Tollesfsen
means by “intellection and free choice.”
If he means the ability to analyze problems, to create and use tools to
solve them, to teach the solutions to young, to plan for the future, develop meaningful
relationships with others, to grieve when those others are lost, to make
personal sacrifices for the benefit of others, to choose between available
options, to delay gratification for a greater reward in the future, to intervene
to help another who is in trouble, or similar tasks, as my series Ask The
Animals addresses (to be resumed next week, but here are parts one and two), he is simply wrong in asserting that humans are unique in
having these abilities. If these abilities
are the ground for a claim to dignity (and justice), then animals have that
claim as well as humans.
But perhaps what he means is the ability to reason
abstractly, to contemplate the meaning of life or the nature of God, and to
make “free choices” between moral rights and wrongs. If so, I fail to see how this attribute in
particular should afford one a greater claim to dignity, or a stronger claim to
“justice,” than all of the abilities listed above.[9]
Indeed, it would seem to me to impose on us an obligation of choosing the "moral right" of treating those of lesser power with dignity and "justice."
The human claim
of dignity, he says, finds its theological expression in the idea that humans
are made in the image of God. [10] I would assert instead, as I explained in my post, Image of God: We Cannot Be Human Without The Animals, that Scripture tells us that humans are made
in the image of God in order to have the capacity to exercise dominion (the two
ideas are in one verse and cannot be separated), that is, to fulfill our
obligations to animals; and that finds
its theological expression when we show God’s character of mercy and compassion
to those who are given into our care – not when we stand on some alleged
“rights” as beings with some perceived “special relationship of friendship with
our Creator.” If we have a special relationship with the Creator, it comes with
obligations, not rights. If we claim
“friendship” with God, we must care for is His. As Jesus never tired of explaining to the
Pharisees, we are not entitled to claim “rights” before God because of special
“status.”
The image in which we are made is that of God who
forsook His status to be born in manager (a place where animals feed), whose
arrival was announced first to shepherds (people who care for animals), who
began his ministry with “the wild beasts,” and who, for the benefit those of
infinity lesser status, died on a cross.
Tollefsen points out that because Jesus became a man, “humankind has a centrality in the
cosmic drama of redemption.” (This seems only fitting since we had a centrality
in its fall, as well. Let's not get too big a head about this, after all.) This gives humans
“specialness” in creation. Perhaps so, but
this “centrality” and “specialness” by definition are features of obligation, not rights. We are to work toward the redemption of all creation, as Tollefsen himself
acknowledges. We have a job to do, a job
that involves recognizing the value of animals to God.[11]
In Part Two of Tollefsen’s critique, he seeks to address
what he believes our obligations to animals are, since (in his view) they are
not obligations of justice. Here, his
real concern comes to light: Tollefsen (like
Camosy) is a strong advocate of the pro-life movement. While Camosy argues that pro-life adherents
should embrace issues of animal welfare because of their similarities,
Tollefsen believes that linking the two (which he believes requires accepting
that animals are equal to humans, something Camosy does not propose) would be
harmful to the pro-life position.[12]
Without wading into the
pro-life/pro-choice controversy, which is beyond the purview of this blog, I
would like to consider what Tollefsen says we do owe animals and why.
But first, I cannot pass by certain strawmen that
Tollefsen sets up with regard to animal welfare.[13] First, he argues that it is not possible to
treat all animals with the same “impartiality” with which we are to treat our
fellow humans. Camosy argues only,
however, that justice requires us to give the animals “what they are owed,” not
equal treatment with humans. What they
are owed depends on how they experience the world, their sentience – so they
are owed a life without cruel treatment, at least.[14] Tollefsen also worries that “the number of
beings crying out for positive attention” would be too much too handle. Even if true, it is not clear to me that is a
reason to limit our moral concern. The
number of human tragedies in the world is too much handle, as well. Whom shall we ignore?
Finally, Tollefsen argues that “[b]ecause resources and
time are finite, [treating animals with justice] would certainly come at the
expense of some time, money, and attention that is now given to the unborn and
to other disadvantaged human beings.”
However, working to end, for example, factory farming is essential for
public health, personal health, world hunger, and the health of the planet on
which humans live. Working to end animal
fighting is working also for the dignity of humans created in God’s image (see
Wilberforce). Working to end testing on animals is working toward faster and
more reliable means of toxicity testing on chemicals, a benefit to human health.
In God’s world order, we are all connected. We cannot harm ourselves by doing the job we
were given at creation. Yes, resources
are scarce; yes, we cannot do it all.
But each of us can do something.
Should we, for example, stop working to end hunger in far flung areas of
the world because there are insufficient resources to help children in need in
our country? Of course not. The idea that we cannot help animals because
there are too many human problems is a false dichotomy. It takes nothing
whatever away from resources to address human problems to, for example, eat
less meat – or give it up altogether -- or buy products not tested on animals, or give the circus a pass.
So, what does Tollefsen say we owe
the animals, since “animals should not be, and indeed cannot be, treated as our
equals; any wrongs that are done in respect of them are not, therefore,
injustices that are done to them.”
Tollefsen here addresses only factory farming, where he acknowledges “something has gone wrong” (emphasis
original). He does acknowledge that
humans should practice kindness toward animals “so as not to be become cruel
human beings.”[15] Beyond that, he suggests that farm animals
should be treated in such a way as to reflect the character of the one who is
caring for them, as a house reflects the character of one who lives there: “we do not like to live in filth, ugliness,
stink, or decay; to which we should add, in light of undercover videos of pig
factories, casual brutality and violence. Our farms should express who we are,
and that ought to mean that they express goodness.” That is about as far as he seems willing to
go. He is clear, however, that this is
not about justice and that individuals who purchase meat from factory farms are
not necessarily doing anything wrong by supporting systems that do not “express
goodness.”
So, are animals “persons?” Do they require “justice?” I am inherently suspicious of any mode of
thinking that seeks to protect one's own at the expense of other. Here, Tollefsen is loath to acknowledge
anything is owed to the animals because he fears it would detract from the
inherent value of human beings (including the unborn) and the resources
necessary to protect them. As Mathew
Scully has pointed out, however, “justice is not a finite commodity, nor are
kindness and love.”[16]
Looking through the lens of Christ, who “did
not count equality with God a thing to be grasped” (Philippians 2:6), I cannot say that animals
are not sufficiently important to be recognized as creatures with their own
inherent value. I cannot say that their suffering is not worth my notice. I continue to believe and to argue that human
value is greatest when we recognize the value of our fellow creatures, and we
live most fully into the image of God when offer them love, mercy, compassion,
and yes, justice.
Animals are each unique individuals
with their own perspective on the world and their own personalities. For me,
that’s enough to call them “people” – someone, not something, as Farm Sanctuary
says. Animals suffer horrifically
through no fault of their own at human hands, for me, that’s enough to call injustice and to say that animals are
owed better. Whether I have used these
words properly to fit into neat philosophical categories, I cannot say. Whether we call animals “persons” and whether
we call what they are owed “justice,” however, is not important. What is important is that we recognize their
inherent value, their right to live life without needless suffering at human hands,
and the obligation of each and every one of us to do something toward that end.
For me the question is not, what does
my dignity as a human being demand that I should receive, but rather, what does
the grace that I have received require that I should give?
[1] It is a very good and
accessible introduction to the issue of why Christians, particularly Catholics,
should care about animal welfare and I commend it to your attention.
[2] Camosy has responded to
Tollefsen’s arguments at Catholic Moral Theology. I am entirely sure Camosy would not agree
with all of my arguments here, and would surely think I have gone too far, but
“go there,” I must.
[3] Camosy, p. 2.
[4] Camosy, p. 7.
[5] Why not, I wonder. What has “specialness” to do with moral worth
or fair treatment? Special to whom?
[6] Again, why?
[7] I suspect Tollefsen would
say that he limits the reach of justice to those of equal “dignity,” not power;
but he limits it to human beings, and human beings have all the power. Therefore, he limits justice to the powerful. We become judge, jury, and executioner in a
system that owes the prisoner no justice.
[8] Middleton, J. Richard. The Liberating Image: Imago Dei in Genesis 1
(Grand Rapids: Brazos Press, 2005), p. 17. See also,
Hall, Douglas John. Imaging God: Dominion As
Stewardship. Eugene: Wipf & Stock, 1986, p. 20, arguing that most
traditional interpretations of imago Dei
are derived not from the context of Scripture but from Greek and Roman
philosophy, subsequently modified by various philosophical and moral
developments in European history. These are both discussed in my post, Why Has The Church Traditionally Taken A Different View?
[9] I would add that humans
have been proven wrong is so many assumptions about animals that I would
hesitate to state categorically that all animals lack the capacity to think
about such things – how would we know if they did? See
also, Marc Bekoff’s discussion of animal “morality,” in his book The Emotional Lives of
Animals: A Leading Scientist Explores Animal Joy, Sorrow, and Empathy – and Why
They Matter (Novato: New World Library, 2007). I will touch on this in my next post.
[10] Since animals also have
the ability to think and analyze and make choices, assuming this is what
Tollefsen means by “intellection and free choice,” this cannot be what it means
to be created in the image of God, since, according to Scripture, that is a uniquely human attribute.
[11] See my post On Image andValue.
[12] In brief, he argues that
because “some human beings” (early fetuses) cannot feel pain, linking
obligations for justice to the ability to feel pain is “deadly to the pro-life
movement.”
[13] As an initial aside, I
note that Tollefsen refers only to “animal liberation.” I wonder whether he is aware of the different
perspectives among those who use the language of “animal liberation,” “animal
rights,” and “animal welfare.”
[14] Tollefsen argues that if
we treat animals with the impartiality with which we are to treat humans, we
would stop driving cars and cutting down trees.
I would point out that we need to take a hard look at these and other
activities for the benefit of humans, as well, as we are rapidly using up the earth’s resources
to the detriment not only to ourselves, but to vulnerable human populations
around the world and future generations.
[15] This suggests, of course,
that the cruelty to the animal, as such, is of no moral relevance.
[16]
Scully,
Matthew. Dominion: The Power of Man, The Suffering of Animals, and The Call
to Mercy. New York, NY: St. Martin's Press, 2002.
7 comments:
I was pleased to see reference to Philippians 2:6 here, as much of what Tollefsen seems to be saying concerning the "dignity of humans made in the image of God" and how this implies that our treatment of animals is not an issue of "justice", seems to rely upon a conception of the imago Dei that is not only shallow, but is insufficiently Christological. I am convinced that our understanding of what it means to be made in the Image of God, is utterly dependent upon an understanding of who God is, and that only in God's full self-disclosure in the life of Christ, is God's character shown clearly to us. In other words, our ability to "image" God, is bound up with our imitation of the character of Christ, the Christ who, according to Phil 2:6, did not consider his own status of equality with God something to be used to his own advantage, and instead entered into solidarity with those of infinitely lesser status (creatures), taking on their nature. That's the Christ who reveals what it is to image God. I'm not sure how to make sense of Tollefsen's "imago Dei" in light of this, except to say that it seems insufficiently Christological, and so insufficiently images God. Thanks so much for this post, I thoroughly enjoy reading your thoughts.
--Allen G. Anderson
Thank you, Allen, for this thoughtful comment. I think you have it exactly right. I especially like this statement: "I am convinced that our understanding of what it means to be made in the Image of God, is utterly dependent upon an understanding of who God is, and that only in God's full self-disclosure in the life of Christ, is God's character shown clearly to us." This seems to me to summarize the concept quite nicely. As for how to understand Tollesfsen's "imago Dei," I was struck when I read his piece by how much it reminded me of Augustine and Aquinas, with their emphasis on human rationality as setting humans apart from the rest of creation. Aquinas, for example, said in his Summa Theologica, “…the love of charity extends to none but God and our neighbor. But the word neighbor cannot be extended to irrational creatures, since they have no fellowship with man in the rational life. Therefore charity does not extend to irrational creatures.” I have been asked to write more about Aquinas and I hope at some point soon to do so, starting with this comment, which seems to me to miss entirely the point of Jesus' teaching on who our neighbor is. But, back to Tollefsen, I think he comes by his understanding of "imago Dei" through an unfortunate element of church history.
Thanks again for your comment and for reading the blog!
Of course, Lois! Thank you for writing such a great blog. I hope to get back into the habit of regularly writing myself, as soon as January is done.
Speaking of Aquinas, if you haven't yet, you should read John Berkman's essay on Aquinas in Creaturely Theology. Berkman, a Catholic and a vegetarian, teases out and develops a much more sophisticated theology of animality, through a closer reading of Aquinas' treatment of the telos, essence (or "ensoulment"), and particular "appetites" (or desires), of non-human animals. He claims that contemporary Thomists, like Herbert McCabe and Marie George, who focus on "theoretical rationality" as a means of "drawing the line" between the human and the animals, are a much less fruitful development of Aquinas' thought than Alasdair MacIntyre, who, according to Berkman, focuses much more on the shared elements of "practical reason". You can find it online at: https://www.academia.edu/3183357/Towards_a_Thomistic_Theology_of_Animality_2009_
^ Allen G. Anderson
Can I ask a very tricky (and maybe too "touchy" of a question), which maybe you've covered in another post, but I just haven't caught up yet: But what about the notion of "persons" as "animals"? There are some who see "evolutionists" and "christians" as contradictory, but I don't necessarily think so (although I don't have a very clear indication on how to reconcile the two). But given the "science" behind evolution, it seems hard to dispute that we "persons"/humans evolved from apes/animals. Kinda throws the notion of Adam & Eve out the window, but there has to be some "genesis" of all living things that I think God did create. Anyway, setting aside the whole Adam & Eve debate and whether we come from apes or Adam/Eve, is there any argument to be made that the question isn't whether animals should be viewed as persons, but whether persons should be viewed as animals. Thus, there's more of a leg to stand on for the argument that persons are more like animals that we think. Thus, instead of trying to separate "us" from "them" or saying that "they" deserve justice because "they" are more like "us," should we be asking the question of whether "we" are more like "them" and therefore owe a debt of justice/gratitude to them out of our historical kinship? Or does that entire notion of the evolutionary aspect totally fly in the face of "humans being made in the image of God"??
Thanks for your comment, LTE. You do, indeed, raise some thorny issues. Like you, I do not see a contradiction between evolution and God's creation of the world. I believe the Book of Genesis tells us truths about God's character, the nature of creation, and God's relationship to the world He created. I think it tells us more about the why of creation than the how. I also agree that there are important lessons to be learned from considering the ways we are like animals. Richard Bauckham, in a book called Living With Other Creatures: Green Exegesis and Theology, emphasizes what he calls "our common creatureliness" with animals. His point is not an evolutionary one, but he seeks to point out that humans and animals are made by the same Creator and have much in common, as a corrective to a view that sets humans above animals. My point, likewise, is not an evolutionary one, but one that seeks to bring home to humans that animal suffering - and happiness - are as real and significant to them as our is to us, and I think that is best done by showing the ways animals are like us, so that we can better relate to them. My hope is to kindle human empathy - with the ultimate objective of kindling human action. Animals suffering is real and it matters, just like our suffering is real and matters. In this context in particular, where Tolefsen is arguing that only "persons" are entitled to justice, I hope to bring animals within that circle. (Although, as I point out in the post, the connection between "person" and an entitlement to justice is not clear to me and in the end I'm less interested in whether animals we call animals "persons" than in how we treat them. They deserve justice and compassion because - like us - they know what it is to suffer.) The equation works in both directions, I think, as both point out the commonalities we share with our fellow creatures. In a theological context, however, I think it would be a distraction to tie those commonalities to evolution, simply because it can be a controversial subject. Regarding your question about image of God, I don't know what do with that in an evolutionary context, but it is something that needs to be addressed in a theological context, since it is uniquely attributed to humans in scripture and sadly has been used to draw a definitive line been humans and everything else. As I have argued in numerous posts here, however, I do not believe that grants us rights over other creatures of God or separates us in some substantive way from them; rather, it imposes on us significant obligations to care for them. Does that help address your questions?
I should clarify that the reason I think putting the issue in an evolutionary context would be a "distraction" is that I believe the analysis - that our creation in God's image imposes on us responsibilities rather than conferring rights and that animals suffer in real and meaningful ways and are otherwise more like us than we have previously supposed - works whether one takes the Genesis creation stories literally or not. So, it is a question on which there are strong feelings on both sides, but it is not one we need to answer in order to understand our obligations to the animals.
Post a Comment